40
REPUBLIC
(AND THE
MULTITUDE
OF THE
POOR)
THE MULTITUDE
OF THE
POOR
41
sive,
unified
social
body of property.
The
poor, in other words, refers
not to those who have nothing but to the wide
multiplicity
of all
those who are inserted in the mechanisms of
social
production re-
gardless of
social
order or property. And this conceptual
conflict
is
also a
political
conflict.
Its productivity is what makes the multitude
of
the poor a real and effective menace for the republic
of
property.
The
essential foundations for understanding the constitutive
relation
between multitude and poverty in this way are established
in
the
political
struggles of seventeenth-century
England.
The term
"multitude"
acquired then an almost technical meaning in popular
political
discourse and pamphlets to name all those gathered to-
gether to
form
a
political
body regardless
of
rank and property.
41
It is
understandable
that
multitude, defined in this way, comes to con-
note the lowest rank of society and the propertyless, since they are
the most
visibly
excluded
from
the dominant
political
bodies, but
really
it is an open,
inclusive
social
body, characterized by its bound-
lessness and its originary
state
of mixture among
social
ranks and
groups. Nahum Tate in Richard the Second (1681), for example, his
rewriting
of Shakespeare, gives an idea of this
mixed
social
body
when
he describes the multitude
with
a
list
of occupations: "Shoo-
maker,
Farrier,
Weaver,
Tanner, Mercer, Brewer, Butcher, Barber, and
infinite
others
with
a Confused
Noise."
42
But even Tate's
multiplic-
ity
of trades,
which
could
serve as a reference to a nascent
working
class,
does not adequately capture the multitude's unbounded na-
ture—its being without regard to rank or property—or its power as
a
social
and
political
body.
We
begin to see more clearly the defining relation to poverty
of
the multitude in the 1647 Putney Debates between the Levellers
and factions of the New
Model
Army
on the
nature
of a new con-
stitution
for England and particularly on the right of suffrage. The
Levellers
argue strongly against the restriction of the vote to those
who
own property.
Colonel
Thomas Rainsborough, speaking for
them, does not use the term "multitude," but in his arguments he
does present the poor as an unbounded and
mixed
political
body. "I
think
that
the poorest he
that
is in
England,"
Rainsborough affirms,-
"has a
life
to
live
as the
greatest
he; and therefore truly, sir, I think it's
clear,
that
every man
that
is to
live
under a government ought first
by
his own consent to put
himself
under
that
government; and I do
think
that
the poorest man in England is not at all bound in a strict
sense
to
that
government
that
he has not had a voice to put
himself
under."
43
Rainsborough is gesturing toward a
political
body when
he refers to this extreme point, "the poorest he," but this is not a
subject
that
is
limited
to or even defined by this lack. Rather this
multitude of the poor is a
political
body without distinction of
property, a
mixed
body
that
is unbounded,
which
would
include
Tate's
list
of tradesmen but not be
limited
to them. For Rainsbor-
ough,
furthermore, this conception of the poor as an open and in-
clusive
political
body directly supports and even necessitates univer-
sal
(or at least extended) suffrage and equal representation. And
indeed
Commissary Ireton of the army, Rainsborough
s
primary in-
terlocutor in the Putney Debates, immediately recognizes the
threat
to the rule
of
property posed by this conception of the
political
sub-
ject. If the vote belongs to everyone, Ireton reasons, why should not
all
property belong to everyone? That is indeed exactly where the
logic
leads.
Tracing
the history of the term "multitude"
presents
a
philo-
logical
conundrum because
there
is
little
textual record of the po-
litical
speech and
writing
of the proponents of the multitude. The
vast majority of references in the archive of seventeenth-century
English
texts are negative, written by those who want to destroy,
denigrate, and deny the multitude. The term is almost always pre-
ceded by a derogatory adjective to double the weight against it: the
lawless
multitude, the headless multitude, the ignorant multitude,
and so forth. Robert
Filmer
and Thomas Hobbes, to cite two prom-
inent figures, seek to deny not
only
the rights of the multitude but
also its very existence.
Filmer,
arguing on scriptural grounds, cast as
if
they were
historical,
contests the claims, made by authors such as
Cardinal
Bellarmine,
that
the multitude because of common natural
right
has the power to determine the
civil
order. Power was given
not equally by natural right to the entire multitude, he contends, but