138
CAPITAL
(AND THE
STRUGGLES OVER COMMON WEALTH)
arrived
at due to environmental disaster, to facilitate the massive
privatization
of public industries, public welfare structures, public
transportation networks, and so forth.
9
Scholars studying subordi-
nated regions and especially
those
countries where
state
structures
are particularly weak, including many
parts
of
Africa,
highlight
cases
in
which neoliberal accumulation involves expropriation of the
common
primarily in the form of natural resources. Extraction pro-
cesses—of
oil,
diamonds, gold, and other materials—thrive in war-
torn regions without sovereign
states
and strong legal structures.
Foreign
capitalist firms, often employing few
local
workers, extract
wealth and
transport
it out of the country in ways reminiscent of
the looting conducted under
colonial
regimes in the
past.
10
It is not
surprising,
then,
that
Marxist
scholars have focused new attention in
recent
years
on the concept of primitive accumulation, since
that
concept allowed
Marx
to understand the accumulation of wealth
outside the capitalist production process, through the direct expro-
priation
of human,
social,
and natural wealth—selling
African
slaves
to plantation holders, for example, or looting gold from the
Ameri-
cas. Contemporary
Marxist
scholars generally deviate from
Marx,
however, as we saw in Part 2, by showing
that
there
is no linear his-
torical
relation between such mechanisms of primitive accumula-
tion
and capitalist production processes, no progressive history of
development in which the former gives way to the latter, but
rather
a
constant
back-and-forth movement in which primitive accumula-
tion
continually
reappears
and coexists with capitalist production.
And
insofar as today's neoliberal economy increasingly favors ac-
cumulation
through expropriation of the common, the concept
of
primitive accumulation becomes an even more central analyti-
cal
tool.
11
This
first guise of the expropriation of the common, which
focuses on neoliberal policies in
terms
of dispossession and expro-
priation,
however,
does
not provide us sufficient
means
to analyze
the organic composition of capital. Although it articulates
fully
the
state
policies and fortunes of dead labor, it says little
about
the other
element necessary for an investigation
of
the organic composition of
capital:
the productivity of
living
labor. To put it differently,
political
METAMORPHOSES
OF THE
COMPOSITION
OF
CAPITAL
139
economists (and the critics of
political
economy) should not be
sat-
isfied
with accounts of neoliberalism
that
pose
capitalist accumula-
tion
as merely or primarily the expropriation of existing wealth.
Capital
is and has to be in its
essence
a productive system
that
gener-
ates
wealth through the labor-power it employs and exploits.
A
second guise of the expropriation of the common, which
centers
on the exploitation of
biopolitical
labor, allows us to
pursue
much
better
a
Marxian
investigation of the organic composition of
capital.
The
three
major
trends
of the transformation of the techni-
cal
composition of labor
that
we outlined earlier all are engaged in
the production of common forms of wealth, such as knowledges,
information,
images, affects, and social relationships, which are sub-
sequently expropriated by capital to
generate
surplus value. Note
right away
that
this second guise refers primarily to a different no-
tion
of the common than
does
the first. The first is a relatively inert,
traditional
notion
that
generally involves natural resources.
Early
modern European social theorists conceive of the common as the
bounty of
nature
available to humanity, including the fertile land to
work
and the fruits of the earth, often posing it in religious
terms
with
scriptural evidence. John
Locke,
for example, proclaims
that
"God,
as
King
David
says,
Psal.
cxv. 16. has given the earth to the
children
of men; given it to mankind in common."
12
The second
notion
of the common is dynamic,
involving
both the product of
labor and the
means
of future production. This common is not only
the earth we
share
but also the languages we
create,
the social prac-
tices we establish, the modes of sociality
that
define our relation-
ships, and so forth. This form of the common
does
not lend
itself
to
a logic of scarcity as
does
the first. "He who receives an idea from
me,"Thomas Jefferson famously remarks, "receives instruction
him-
self
without lessening mine; as he who lights his
taper
at mine,
receives light without darkening me."
13
The expropriation of this
second form of the common—-the
artificial
common or, really, the
common
that
blurs the
division
between
nature
and culture—is the
key
to understanding the new forms of exploitation of
biopolitical
labor.
When
analyzing
biopolitical
production we
find
ourselves be-