60
POST-KANTIAN IDEALIST SYSTEMS
whereas the theory of rights and of political society is concerned
with the external relations between human beings. Further,
if
the
comment is made
that
the doctrine of rights can be regarded as
applied ethics, in the sense
that
it is deducible as an application
of
the moral law, Fichte refuses to admit the
truth
of this contention.
The fact
that
I have a right does not necessarily mean
that
I am
under an obligation to exercise it. And the common good may
demand on occasion a curtailment of or limitation on the exercise
of rights.
But
the moral law is categorical:
it
simply says, 'Do this'
or 'Do not do
that'.
Hence the system of rights is not deducible
from the moral law, though
we
are, of course, morally obliged to
respect the system of rights as established in a community.
In
this sense the moral law adds a further sanction to rights,
but
it is
not their initial source.
In
Hegel's opinion Fichte did not really succeed in overcoming
the formalism of the Kantian ethics, even
iihe
provided some of
the material for doing
so.
And
it
was indeed Hegel rather
than
Fichte who synthesized the concepts
of
right, interior morality and
society in the general concept
of
man's ethical life.
But
the chief
reason why I have dwelt in the first section
of'this
chapter on
Fiehte's distinction between the doctrine of rights and ethical
theory is
that
I propose to
treat
of the philosopher's moral theory
before outlining his theory of rights
and
of the State. And this
procedure might otherwise give the erroneous impression
that
Fichte regarded the theory of rights as a deduction from the moral
law.
2.
A man can have knowledge, Fichte says,
of
his moral nature,
of his subjection to a moral imperative, in two ways.
In
the first
place he can possess this knowledge on the level of common moral
consciousness.
That
is to say, he can be aware through his conscience
of a moral imperative telling him to do this or not to do that. And
this immediate awareness is quite sufficient for a knowledge
of
one's
duties and for moral behaviour.
In
the second place a man can
assume the ordinary moral consciousness as something given and
inquire into its grounds. And a systematic deduction of the moral
consciousness from its roots in the ego is the science
of
ethics and
provides 'learned knowledge'.1
In
one sense, of course, this
learned knowledge leaves everything
as
it
was before.
It
does not
create obligation, nor does
it
substitute a new set of duties for
those
of
which one is already aware through conscience.
It
will not
1
F,
IV, p.
122;
M,
II,
p.
516.
FICHTE
(2)
6I
give a
man
a moral nature,
But
it
can enable him to understand
his moral nature.
3.
What
is meant
by
man's moral nature? Fichte tells us
that
there is in man
an
impulsion to perform certain actions simply for
the
sake of performing them, without regard
to
external purposes
or
ends, and to leave undone other actions simply for
the
sake of
leaving them undone, again without regard to external purposes
or
ends. And the
nature
of man in
so
far as this impulsion necessarily
manifests itself within him is his 'moral or ethical nature'.
1
To
understand the grounds of this moral nature is the task of
ethics.
The ego is activity, striving. And as
we
saw when considering
the
practical deduction of consciousness, the basic form taken
by
the striving which constitutes the ego is infra-conscious impulse
or
drive. Hence from one point
of
view man
is
a system of impulses,
the impulse which can be ascribed to the system as a whole being
that
of self-preservation. Considered in this light, man can be
described as an organized product of Nature. And as conscious of
myself as a system
of
impulses I can say,
'I
find myself as an
organized product of Nature.'2
That
is to say, I posit or affirm
myself as being this when I consider myself as object.
But
man is also intelligence, a subject of consciousness. And as
subject of consciousness the ego necessarily tends or is impelled to
determine itself through itself alone;
that
is, it
is
a striving after
complete freedom and independence. Inasmuch, therefore, as the
natural impulses
and
desires which belong to man as a product of
Nature aim
at
satisfaction through some relation to a determinate
natural object and consequently appear to depend on the object,
we
understandably contrast these impulses with the spiritUal
impulse of the ego as intelligence, the impulse,
that
is to say, to
complete self-determination. We speak of lower
and
higher desires,
of the sphere of necessity and the sphere of freedom, and introduce
a dichotomy into human nature.
Fichte does not deny,
of
course,
that
such distinctions have, so
to speak, a cash value. For one can look
at
man
from two points of
view, as object and as subject.
As
we
have seen, I can be conscious
of myself as an object
in
Nature, as an organized product of
Nature, and I can be aware of myself as a subject for whose
consciousness Nature, including myself as object, exists. To this
1
F,
IV, p.
13;
M,
II,
p.
407.
I F, IV, p.
122;
M,
II,
p
..
~16.