3
22
REACTION AGAINST METAPHYSICAL IDEALISM
the economic structure
of
society'. 1
In
this passage the economic
structure of a society is indeed identified with the
totality
of its
productive relations.
But
inasmuch as these relations are said
to
correspond with a certain level of development of the productive
forces of the society in question, and inasmuch as the emergence of
conflicts between the productive forces
and
the productive
relations in a given society
is
an essential feature in Marx's picture
of human history, it
is
obvious
that
we
must distinguish two main
elements in the economic structure
of
society, a structure which is
also described
by
Marx as a mode of production (Produktionsweise).
The term 'material forces of production' (or 'material productive
powers') obviously covers all the material things which are used
by
man as artificial instruments in his productive activity,
that
is, in
the satisfaction
of
his physical needs, from primitive flint instru-
ments up to the most complicated modern machinery.
It
also
includes natural forces in
so
far as they are used
by
man in the
process of production. And the term can apparently also cover all
such objects as are required for productive activity, even
if
they do
not enter into
it
directly.
2
Now,
if
the term is applied exclusively to things distinct from
man himself, man is obviously presupposed. Marx tends
to
speak
of the forces of production as doing this or
that,
but
he is not so
stupid as to suppose
that
these forces develop themselves without
any human agency. 'The first condition of all human history is
naturally the existence of living human individuals.'3 And in the
Communist Manifesto he speaks of the bourgeoisie as revolutioniz-
ing the instruments of production
and
thereby the productive
relations. However, in the
German Ideology he remarks
that
the
production of life, whether of one's own life
by
work or of
that
of
another through procreation, always involves a social relation, in
the
sense of the collaboration of several individuals. And after
observing
that
it
follows from this
that
a given mode of production
is always linked to a given
mode of collaboration, he asserts
that
this mode of collaboration is itself a 'productive force'.4 He means,
of course,
that
the social relation between men in the process of
production can itself react on men's needs
and
on the productive
forces.
But
if the mode
of
collaboration in the labour-process can
be reckoned as a productive force, there seems to be no reason why,
1
zu,
K,itik
de, polilische1l Oek01l0mie, p
..
x (I, p. 363).
I Cf. Das Kapital,
I,
p.
143
(I,
pp. 172-3)
• Deutsche Ideologie, W,
Ill,
p.
20
(p. 7).
• Ibid., p. 30 (p. 18).
THE
TRANSFORMATION
OF
IDEALISM
(2)
for example, the proletariat should not be accounted a productive
force, even if the term is generally used
by
Marx for instruments or
means
of
production rather
than
for man himself.
1
In
any
case
it
is
notoriously difficult to pin him down to a precise
and
universal use
of such terms.
The term 'productive relations' means above
all property-
relations. Indeed, in the
Critique
of
Political Economy
we
are told
that
'property relations' (Eigentumsverhaltnisse)
is
simply a juristic
expression for 'productive relations'.
2 However, in general the
term
'productive relations' refers to the social relations between
men as involved in the labour-process.
As
we
have seen, these
relations are said to depend on the stage
of
development of the
productive forces. And
t\le two together constitute the economic
substructure.
This economic substructure is said
to
condition the super-
structure. 'The mode of production
of
material life conditions the
social, political
and
mental (geistigen) life-process in general.
It
is
not the consciousness of human beings which determines their
being,
but
it is, on the contrary, their social being which determines
their consciousness.'3 Obviously, the statement
that
the economic
substructure 'conditions'
(bedingt) the superstructure is ambiguous.
The statement is not
at
all startling
if
it
is taken in a very weak
sense.
It
becomes interesting only in proportion as the meaning
of
the term 'conditions' approaches 'determines'. And
it
has indeed
frequently been taken in this strong sense. Thus it has been main-
tained, for example,
that
the
celestial hierarchy (from God down
to the choirs
of
angels
and
the company
of
the saints)
of
mediaeval
theology was simply an ideological reflection
of
the mediaeval
feudal structure which was itself determined
by
economic factors .
. Again, the rise of the bourgeoisie
and
the arrival of the capitalist
mode of production were reflected in the transition from
Catholi-
cism to Protestantism. According to Engels the Calvinist doctrine
of predestination reflected the supposed economic fact
that
in
commercial competition success or failure does
not
depend on
personal merits
but
on incomprehensible and uncontrollable
economic powers.
Yet it was also Engels who protested
that
the
doctrine of Marx
and
himself
had
been misunderstood. They had
never meant
that
man's ideas are simply a pale reflection of
1
In
The Pove,ty
of
Philosophy Marx
says
explicitly
that
the
revolutionary
proletariat
is
the
greatest
of all
productive
forces. See below, p. 328.
I
Zu"
K"itik de, politische1l Oek01l0mie, p. x (I, p. 363),
I Ibid., p.
xi
(I,
p. 363).