A simple illustration shows how parameters contribute to making progress
and solving problems. Conceive of UG as a set of universal principles. If
universal, every language must hav e the properties specified in the principle.
One candidate for such a principle is that all languages must form phrases that
consist of a ‘head’ (a lexical item of some category, such as A[djective/…dverb]
or V[erb]) and a complement, which is itself a phrase, and may be null.
Formalizing a bit, XP = X – YP, with ‘X’ and ‘Y’ being any of V, A,
P[reposition/postposition], D[eterminer]. This is primitive, but it will do for
illustration purposes. Think then of this principle as being parameterized, as
allowing options. The options are repres ented in the formula’s ‘-’, which is
unordered. If unorder ed, heads in a language could be before their comple-
ments, or after. English is a “head first” language, so that a VP comes out “call
the dog.” Japanese (Miskito, etc.) is a “head final/last” language, so its phrases
put heads after complements. If English were head-last, the example would
come out: “the dog call.” This parametric option – and others – can be seen as
something like a switch that in one position yields a head-first language and in
the other, a head-last. Assume (plausibly) a finite, and presumably small
number of linguistic parameters. Specifying the full set of linguistic principles
and their parameters would, then define the possible structures of the class of all
natural languages, each of which is biologically and physically possible. A
specification of this sort would ‘say’ what a biologically/physically possible
structure for a natural language could be. If there were 12 parameters and they
were binary and independent of one another, there could be 2
12
structurally
different languages. Assuming all this, principles and parameters offer very
useful descriptive tools; they allow for the description of all possible natural
languages with regard to at least their structural and sound differences, allowing
a reduced UG to offer adequate descriptions of any possible natural language.
As indicated, they also offer a solution to Plato’s Problem, a dominant
explanatory problem that, until solved, blocks dealing with other explanatory
issues. Conceive of a parameter amounting to something like a toggle or switch;
in the case of the illust ration, when the switch is in one position, one has a
head-first language, when in the other, a head-last. Think then of a major part of
language acquisition as a matter of setting switches in one of the few positions
that each parameter allows – in simple cases, position 1 or 2. This picture does
not speak to lexical acquisition – or at least, not directly. Language acquisition
requires acquiring a vocabulary too. But it does make a major contribution to the
task of solving Plato’s Problem with regard to language – the combinatory
system. It also suits the facts. There is evidence in favor of the idea that children
do set parameters in the course of developing a language. Some of the most
interesting evidence is found in the fact that at specific stages of language
development, children’s minds ‘experiment’ with parameter settings, trying
out settings that are not typical of the languages spoken in their communities,
Introduction to the third edition 31