Given such beliefs about the mind and its study, the RR advocate is likely to
maintain – as suggested above – that the view of the world that one gets through
the lens of our innate concepts and combinatory principles owes more to the
characters of our concepts and combi natory principles than it does to how the
world might be ‘in itself’. To put a label on this kind of view, I will call it (a form
of) const ructivism: our minds ‘make’ the world, rather than the other way
around. I mention it here to underscore the difference between the RR camp
and the empiricist one. For empiricists believe that in the case of most concepts
(perhaps not ‘pure’ sensory ones) and combinatory principles, the world shapes
the mind.
The RRs ’ opponents, the empiricists, hold that most of the concepts
expressed in natural languages (DOG, HOUSE, WASH…) and the combinatory
principles that place them in understandable sentences are not innate, but rather
learned. Perhaps they are assemblies of perceptual ‘features’ (Locke, Prinz
(2002)), specific kinds of roles constituted by the ‘moves’ (inferences) people
engage in when exercising social pract ices, ‘connection weights’ in neural nets,
and so on. However construed, concepts and “rules” are learned by engaging
some kind of generalized learning procedu re (hypothesis formation and testing,
association, training procedures, behaviorist conditioning…) that after repeti-
tion and ‘feedback ’ in the form of positive and negative ‘evidence’ comes to
converge on what society, the experimenter, ‘the world’, or some other assumed
judge of meeting a criterion accepts. However construed, the empiricist believes
that the environment, including society, makes and shapes concepts and the
principles (“rules”) of their combination through some sort of generalized
learning procedure, a procedure that usually involves not just (a lot of) sensory
or other low-level input and/or data, but a trial-and-error procedure of some sort,
where error is corrected by some kind of ‘negative evidence’ [“that’s not right;”
pain/punishment on a behaviorist version of empiricism], perhaps provided by
parents or instructors, perhaps even (it is claimed) by the lack of data. Because
the empiricist holds that such procedures are sufficient to learn the thousands of
concepts that four-year-olds have available, and to learn the combinatory
principles and structural constraints of a local language, the empiricists must
assume that much of the child’s early life and use of language is devoted to
focused data-gathering and training sessions that consist in getting the child to
conform to the “speech habits,”‘proper’ (epistemically appropriate, etc.) appli-
cations, or uses of concepts the child’s trainers want it to exhibi t. For otherwise
one
would find – contrary to fact – children acquiring language and many
thousands of concepts at very different times (depend ing on training, the
resources of trainers, native intelligence, interest and devotion to duty…),
going through very different stages of development, and so on. However the
story is told, empiricists are anti nativist and externalist: they maintain that
concepts such as those mentioned above and the combinatory principles or
16 Introduction to the third edition