W. V. o. Quine has suggested that a physical object is “the aggre-
gate material content of any portion of space-time, however ragged and
discontinuous.”
4
on the face of it, this proposal looks circular, since we
are taking ‘material’ to be synonymous with ‘physical’. But it may be pos-
sible to avoid this problem simply by subtracting the word ‘material’ from
Quine’s suggestion, leaving us with a proposal according to which a phys-
ical object is the content of any portion of space-time.
This proposal has some plausible consequences, but it also comes with
some noteworthy metaphysical baggage. For this Quinean account entails
a thesis called Universalism (see below), according to which (roughly) for
any group of objects, there is a further object whose parts are the mem-
bers of that group. Thus, for example, according to Universalism, there is
an object whose parts are your head, the president’s shoes, and a single
quark from the surface of the moon. As we will see in 8.8 below, there are
some interesting arguments in support of Universalism; but it is neverthe-
less a highly controversial thesis. Thus, the fact that our Quinean account
of physical objects entails Universalism counts as a significant cost of that
account.
A further problem for the Quinean view is that it may prove impossible,
on that view, to distinguish between a particular physical object, such as a
ball, say, and any event that is spatio-temporally coincident with that ball,
such as the ball’s history. What’s more, on certain theories of universals, it
may also prove impossible to distinguish between the ball and its various
life-long properties. (Perhaps this problem is the reason Quine included
the word ‘material’ in his statement of the view in the first place.)
Peter van Inwagen has suggested an alternative account of physical
objects.
5
According to van Inwagen, there is a certain family of proper-
ties – such as being located in space, having spatial extension, persisting
through time, being able to move about in space, having a surface, hav-
ing mass, being made of matter, and so on – that are associated with the
concept of a physical object. Van Inwagen further suggests that the latter
concept is an imprecise one, and that the extent to which an object exem-
plifies all or most of the concepts on the associated list is the extent to
which that object is a physical object.
4
Quine, “Whither Physical objects?,” p. 497.
5
van Inwagen, Material Beings, p. 17.