
The
Pauli principle
57
pictures
of
atomic orbitals.
If
two electrons occupy an atomic orbital,
how
can
we
distinguish between them? We cannot now measure the coor·
dinates
of
the
two
electrons
in
the same way that we can measure the
coordinates
of
apples
on
n:JY
desk. The fact
is
that the electrons, like all
quantum
wave-particles,
are
indistinguishable.
The
statistics
of
counting distinguishable particles are completely dif·
ferent from those for counting indistinguishable particles. Remember
from Section
L I (and Appendix A) that Planck decided
to
use Bolti·
mann's
statistical
approach
in
deriving his radiation law. However,
,
instead
of
assuming his energy elements to be distinguishable (as
Boltzmann had always assumed when applying
his methods to atoms
and
molecules) Planck purposefully made them indistinguishable. Paul
Ehrenfest pointed
om
in
1911
that in doing this, Planck had given his
quanta
properties that were simply impossible for classical particles.
Of
course.
photons
and electrons are not classical particles. They possess
wave· like properties too,
and
these properties lead
to
behaviour that
is
/'
completely counter-intuitive if
we
try to think
of
photons
and
electrons
as tiny,
sdf-contained
particles,
Before
we
tie ourselves in knots,
let
us
take a look at what indis-
tinguishability
means in terms
of
state vectors.
The
state vector for a
two-particle state (a
state consisting
of
two electrons, for example)
is
just
the product
of
the state vectors
of
the two particles. Thus,
if
particle
I is described by the state vector
l1fm),
and particle 2
is
described by
the
state
vector
1""0)'
the appropriate product state
can
be written
1
1/;~
> 11/;;), where the superscripts indicate the individual particles.
But these particles are supposed to be indistinguishable. We bave
labelled
the particles as I
and
2 but
if
they are indeed indistinguishable
we
have
nO
way
of
telling them
apart.
We can certainly distinguish bet·
ween
the
possible
quantum
states
l1fm)
and
I if;,} since they can corres·
pond
to states with different
quantum
numbers, energies, angular
momenta
etc,
but
we
cannot tell experimentally which particle
is
in which
state.
Thus,
the product I
1/;;)
1
1/;~}
is
just as acceptable as I
II'
~)
I if;;),
(Note that the order in which
we
write the functions down
is
irrelevant,
I
,p;,.)
I if;;>
==
I if;;)
l,p;.)·)
Because both
of
these product slate vectors are equally 'correct',
we have
to
assume
that
we
can write a total two-particle state vector,
denoted
I '1'''), as a linear 5uperpesition
of
both these possibilities:
(2.34)
This
mixture must contain equal proportions
of
each product state
(because
they must be equally possible), and so it follows that
Icm,i
'"
iC,ml.
Furthermore,
if we assume that
Ii'''>
is
normalized,
Icm,l' +
Icoml'
=
I,
and
so
Icm,l
=
icomi
=
IIh.