Adorno wrote in response to what he perceived to be the increasing inOuence of
Heideggerian vocabulary in post-war Germany. As we've seen, Heidegger tried to a1ribute
special signiKcance to familiar terms by claiming unfamiliar
meanings for them through his dis.nc.ve etymologies. Adorno began his book with reference
to the nineteenth century philosopher S0ren Kierkegaard's 'leap of faith'; a sugges.on that
religious faith relies on people not only pledging belief but being willing to rely on it, to jump
the abyss certain of landing on the other side. To Adorno, Heidegger's vocabulary required a
similar leap of faith. And, to him, it's unjus.Ked. He described Heideggerian language as a cult
(1986, 5). For him, the philosopher's jargon cloaked unsubstan.ated argument with the
'pretence of deep human emo.on' (1986, 6). Those who follow it do so rather like those who
admire the emperor's new clothes. For Adorno, par.cular words are larded with pathos in an
a1empt to dupe the reader into belief.
It was the conjunc.on of Heidegger's authen.city claims with his way of speaking which
Adorno found most problema.c. He suggested that, while Heidegger's vocabulary claimed to
validate the experiences of everyday life over ideal objects or ideas, it merely set up an
alterna.ve ideal which was just as distant from people. InOuenced by the work of Karl Marx,
Adorno felt that Heideggerian terminology relied upon, and was only capable of describing, a
honeyed domes.city; like the Black Forest farm where agrarian subsistence was supposedly a
constant and happy existence for successive genera.ons. To him, Heidegger's vocabulary of
ideal dwelling had no room for reali.es of poverty. It was incapable of expressing class-ridden
inequality, its rosy expressions unable to deal with the priva.ons of inequity and conOict.
Especially in the post-war German context, Adorno worried that Heidegger's jargon all too
easily allowed a middle-class belief in the normality of pet bourgeois domes.c life; its
authen.city claims admi"ng the sugges.on that comfortable domes.city remained a safe and
reliable constant in Germany before, during and a+er the Nazi era, a way of life temporarily
interrupted by the unpleasantness of war (1986, 22). To him, Heidegger's vocabulary of
authen.city validated and reinstated a roman.c complacency. Worse, its polarising
authen.city claims enabled a con.nua.on of the fascist mindset.
Heidegger's sympathisers would dispute the links made between his etymologies and fascist
ideology. Yet, the model of architecture summarised in '. . . poe.cally, Man dwells . . .' as
'authen.c' poe.c dwelling, which Heidegger
also located in past manifesta.on in the Black Forest farmhouse, is clearly advocated without
compromise. For him, authen.c architecture subscribes to that model and inauthen.c
architecture does not. In the scheme of Adorno's cri.que, the ul.mate authen.city claims are
PLACING HEIDEGGER