§2. Butler’s Argument contra Hedonistic Egoism
While Butler’s argument contra hedonistic egoism (in pars. 4–7, with sup-
plementary observations elsewhere)
4
is not altogether successful, he does
make several essential points which pave the way for a useful refutation.
These points are picked up by later writers (e.g., Hume, Enquiry, App.IIof
An Enquiry into the Principles of Morals, and Bradley in Ethical Studies, Essay
VII, esp. pp. 251–276).
5
Bradley’s argument is quite decisive, I think. Thus,
rather than set out and comment upon Butler’s argument as he presents it,
I shall sketch in brief form what I take to be a version of Bradley’s argu-
ment and then point out what Butler contributed to it. This will help us to
see at the same time where Butler’s formulations may need correction.
(1) Let’s begin by noting certain features of the actions of reasonable
and rational agents. We assume that agents can select between various al-
ternative actions, depending on their circumstances and the various con-
straints to which they are subject. The class of alternatives is within their
powers: they are able to do and not to do any of these actions. Which avail-
able action an agent will do depends upon the agent’s beliefs, desires, and
assessment of the consequences of the possible action, as understood by
the agent. Here “desires” is a stand-in for Butler’s appetites, affections, and
passions both general and particular, and in these we have to include what
in the passage just quoted Butler called the “affection to and pursuit of
what is right and good, as such.” Note that Butler calls this an affection.
(2) Next, think of the object of desire as that state of affairs the bringing
about of which is the aim of the desire. When this object is brought about,
we say the desire is fulfilled; it has achieved its aim by realizing its object.
Let’s say that a desire is gratified when the agent knows, or reasonably be-
lieves or experiences, that the desire is fulfilled.
The language here has to be rephrased a bit to accommodate desires to
participate in or to engage in various activities, or to do various things, for
their own sake. Sometimes it is awkward to think of activities as states of
affairs, even if by certain locutions we can do this. We should also intro-
duce the notion of a final desire as, for example, the desire to engage in an
[ 441 ]
Five Lectures on Joseph Butler
4. Cf. especially the statement of one basic psychological principle in par. 13.
5. F. H. Bradley, Ethical Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1927).
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY
EXAM COPY