prided himself on his mimesis, his relentless imitations of action
(although he often included narrative asides), but he was always willing
to sacrifice realism for the sake of comic effect or entertainment.
Like James and Trilling, Booth is vigorously opposed to prescrip-
tions in advance about realism. Booth sees James as committed to that
‘dissimulation’ discussed in the first section of this chapter. Yet James
certainly did not have a one-size-fits-all narrative strategy. In a nutshell,
Booth’s position is that there should not be ‘a general rhetoric in the
service of realism’, but ‘a particular rhetoric for the most intense
experience of distinctive effects’ (1961: 50). Horses for courses, we
might say. In the same way that Aristotle did not rule out diegesis,
objecting only to its excessive use, Booth argues that extraneous
commentary may be necessary for the sake of clarity and clarification
in some narrative situations, but obtrusive and unwelcome in others.
This takes us back not only to the concept of organic form, but to one
of its first proponents, Aristotle. The unity of a text was critical for
Aristotle. As a biologist, his model for that unity was the body. Plays
in particular, which is what he had in mind in his Poetics, should repre-
sent, or imitate, a ‘unified action’, so that they produce their ‘proper
pleasure like a single whole living creature’ (Aristotle 1972: 123). The
point about bodies, or organisms, however, is not just that they are
organized, but that they are organized for diverse purposes and can
adapt, physically and mentally, to particular environments.
There are few, if any, rules that can be handed down in advance
for the unique experiences an individual encounters. The same goes
for the novel. The blanket rule that the intrinsic method will always
serve the purposes of realism better is absurd: it implies that realism
(in ways that Booth’s taxonomy has falsified) is a monolithic category
and overlooks the extent to which communication, again the main
purpose of the novel for Booth, should have as its goal successful
transmission and reception in particular contexts. For Booth, every
element of the narrative model on p. 16 is part of this overall trans-
action. But as we saw at the end of the last chapter, Booth’s flexi-
bility is a form of the dissimulation of which he accuses James.
By the end of The Rhetoric of Fiction, as will emerge in the final chapter,
it is clear that Booth prefers the extrinsic to the intrinsic method,
even though he wants to deny the validity of the distinction. This
is why he attacks James for wanting to conceal the illusory nature of
his realism.
111
4
6
7
9
0
1
4
6
7
111
9
0
4
6
7
9
0111
4
6
7
911
REALISM AND REPRESENTATION
53