130 victorian england: ruskin, swinburne, pater
attentively. For the English critics, it is true, modern-life subject-
matter per se is relatively unimportant; that may be partly to do with the
different circumstances in England, where modern-life subject-matter
was readily accepted by traditionalist critics, and was even, by the 1860s,
somewhat passé. But the fundamental premise of English art for art’s
sake, that art delivers its value in itself, in the present ‘moment’, is akin
to Baudelaire’s construction of ‘modernity’ in a more profound sense.
Moreover, the writings of Swinburne and Pater take up an insight of
Baudelaire’s essay that was perhaps less influential in France: ‘mod-
ernity’ is an aspect of all art, not just the art of the most recent period.
Baudelaire shows how Guys’s drawings, the most ‘modern’ works we
can imagine, already have an element of antiquity. The essays in Pater’s
Renaissance point out the corollary: such a work as Leonardo’s Mona
Lisa has lasting value only because it contains the element of ‘mod-
ernity’, which we rediscover in the ‘moment’ of our aesthetic experience
of it (if we do not, Baudelaire would surely agree, it makes no difference
whether the work was made ten minutes or ten centuries ago). The
Mona Lisa [93], when Pater looks at it, is as ‘modern’ as Guys’s draw-
ings [60] or Rossetti’s paintings [67, 75] are when we look at them.
The theory of ‘art for art’s sake’ was, as the phrase indicates, in some
sense a translation into English of the French l’art pour l’art; the Fran-
cophile Swinburne, although he was not the first critic to use the
English phrase, was certainly the one to establish it as a key term for
English criticism.
30
But English art for art’s sake was different from
French l’art pour l’art, and in some ways more radical. As we have seen,
the French writers were not quite able to relinquish the Christian or
Platonic hope that a ‘pure’ art would ultimately lead beyond itself, to
spiritual transcendence. By giving up this aspiration, Swinburne and
Pater were able to advance a more consistent and rigorous version of art
for art’s sake, one in which art had really to justify itself on its own
terms, in the ‘manner of doing a thing’ or in the ‘moment’ as it passes,
without recourse to any divine or spiritual sanction.
For Pater, indeed, it is precisely the ‘passing’ quality of the artistic
moment that gives it positive value. Throughout his writings, Pater
resolutely opposes any form of dogmatism; ‘stereotype’ and ‘fixed prin-
ciples’ are anathema to him.
31
Art for him is the most powerful counter
to dogma; it is a guarantee of the relative, the contingent, the fugitive
and transitory. Pater uses the terminology of Baudelaire’s ‘The Painter
of Modern Life’, but the difference is clear. Pater rejects the ‘absolute’
or ‘eternal’ aspect of Baudelairean beauty, and puts his entire faith in
the ‘fugitive’ or ‘contingent’ aspect. ‘Every moment some form grows
perfect in hand or face’, he writes in the Conclusion to The Renaissance:
‘some tone on the hills or the sea is choicer than the rest; some mood of
passion or insight or intellectual excitement is irresistibly real and
attractive to us,—for that moment only.’
32