18 Jeffrey Stout
guided by in this practice, however fallibly, are norms of the people, by
the people, and for the people participating in the practice. But those
norms have to do with getting things right in a sense of ‘right’ that
cannot be reduced to communal agreement.
The philosophers I am calling revisionist pragmatists are all trying to
get both of these points adequately stated in a single account of inquiry.
However self-reliant the practice of inquiry may be, they are saying,
there need be nothing narcissistic about it, for it essentially involves an
attempt to do descriptive justice to the subject matter being discussed. It
is therefore crucial not only to avoid the metaphysical quagmire caused
by viewing truth as a substantial something capable of definition, but also
to avoid reducing objectivity to solidarity, understood as a sociological
fact. Getting one’s subject matter right is not the same thing as achieving
agreement with one’s fellow inquirers. For even if we could not all be
wrong about most things, as Davidson and Rorty have claimed, we could
still all be wrong about anything in particular. The idea of getting one’s
subject matter right that Rorty embraces at Ramberg’s urging does not
boil down to the idea of getting ‘as much intersubjective agreement as
possible’ (Rorty 1991: 23). Accepting the former idea involves adopting
a normative stance that can achieve expression only in the vocabulary
of agency, whereas accepting the latter idea does not. Losing sight of
this distinction—or, worse still, deliberately trying to efface it—is what
turns pragmatic self-reliance into narcissism, because it leaves us able
to focus only on facts about ourselves as a community of inquiry while
eliminating the normative notion of objectivity that our community
requires us to employ. (A further extreme would be solipsism, by
which Rorty is not similarly tempted.) Ramberg’s affirmation of the
inescapability and irreducibility of an essentially normative vocabulary
of agency, as an essential background to the enterprise of descriptive
inquiry, helps keep the distinction in view.
Getting something right, in short, turns out to be among the
human interests that need to be taken into account in an acceptably
anthropocentric conception of inquiry as a social practice. If inquiry is
to be understood pragmatically, as a set of human activities answerable
only to human interests, and we grant that getting something right is
among the human interests implicitly at work in these very activities,
then we can have our pragmatism and our objectivity too—that is
to say, pragmatism without narcissism. This, I believe, is the point
that revisionists have been trying to make all along. It is important, in
making this point, to avoid interpreting the notion of getting something