J. F. Blumenbach to J. C. Prichard, race had been a patently visible but
highly mutable feature. While it was closely associated with culture,
morality, and intelligence, it was seen as alterable through racial mixing,
environment, or the inheritance of acquired characteristics, within a
relatively short period of time. For the defenders of slavery, by contrast,
race was an indelible and immutable attribute. Over many generations the
races had been preserved, virtuall y as separate species, and they were
incapable of interbreeding for any length of time. All too conveniently,
according to this view, some races (notably Anglo- Saxons) were destined
by nature to be masters, while others (most notably black Africans) were
preordained to be slaves. The abolition of slavery, first in the British
colonies and later in the United States, tended to discredit these “poly-
genist” views. Nevertheless during the 1860s, 1870s, and 1880s there was
no simple return to the Prichardian–Macaulayite position. On the con-
trary, the advent of evolution opened the way to a completely new
approach to race, which more effectively addressed the needs of the late
Victorian capitalist polity and society, and was neither strictly polygenist
nor monogenist in the old raciall y absolutist terms.
9
In the new framework, race was treated as neither immutable nor
incidental, but as a longue durée historical phenomenon that developed
(at least potentially) in progressive terms. While J. S. Mill, H. T. Buckle,
and a few other students of progress steered clear of both “race” and
“evolution,” most others came to embrac e the connection between them
as fou ndational to a chastened liberalism, appropriate for an increasingly
biologistic age. By making “race” progressive, evolution rendered it safe
for liberalism. Yet by limiting “progress” to race, evolution tempered its
velocity. There is a certain irony in the fact that, at the very moment when
“progress” was disappearing from grand historical narratives, such as those
of Froude, it was creeping into a new kind of bio-social evolutionary theory,
where it could endorse the superiority of Anglo-Saxon civilization in a more
formidable “scientific” manner and reaffirm the civilizing possibilities for
lesser peoples, albeit in gradual, imperially directed ways.
10
9
For early nineteenth-century liberal approaches, see J. C. Prichard, Researches in the
Physical History of Man, ed. and with introduction by George Stocking (Chicago, 1973);
John C. Greene, The Death of Adam: Evolution and its Impact on Western Thought (Ames,
1959), 175–247; George Stocking, Victorian Anthropology (New York, 1987), 1–77. For
polygenism, see Robert Knox, The Races of Man [1850] (London, 1862); Stepan, The Idea
of Race in Science,20–82; Christine Bolt, Victorian Attitudes to Race (London, 1971); and
Stocking, Victorian Anthropology,78–143.
10
Stocking, Victorian Anthropology, 144–273; Theodore Koditschek, “Capitalism, Race and
Evolution in Imperial Britain: 1850–1900,” in Theodore Koditschek, Sundiata Cha-Jua,
and Helen Neville (eds.), Race Struggles (Champaign-Urbana, 2009), 48–79.
The advent of evolution and longue durée history 211