1 Modeling and the Future of Science Learning 7
Confrey, 2010). It is this highly pragmatic use of models that are known to pos-
sess quite significant limitations that distinguishes scientists from students (Shen &
Confrey, 2010; Williamson & Abraham, 1995). Hence, a key aspect of the nature
of science, as it pertains to models and modeling, is that scientists understand the
nature of models and see models in a very functional, utilitarian, manner (Portides,
2007). They instinctively, or as a result of their training, recognize that models
are intended to serve the user and frequently require modification (e.g., when new
experimental data are obtained, see Borges & Gilbert, 1999). Grosslight, Unger, J ay,
and Smith (1991) observe that one reason for this difference between scientists and
students is that students and non-scientists tend to think of models in concrete terms,
effectively as scale models of reality (see also, Abell & Roth, 1992; Bent, 1984b;
Carr, 1984; Clement, 1998), and thus do not appreciate their limitations (Ogan-
Bekiroglu, 2007). This, it is argued, occurs because some well-known models have
proven spectacularly successful. Examples include the Watson–Crick model for t he
structure of DNA (Rodley & Reanny, 1977; Watson & Crick, 1953), Einstein’s rela-
tivity (Clark, 1973; Kline, 1985), and Schrödinger’s wave-mechanical model of the
atom (Kline, 1985; Moore, 1989). What this may mean is that successful models
are so powerful at explaining well-understood observationsthat they end up being
regarded as “facts” (Schrader, 1984). In other words, a student or novice may con-
fuse a highly successful, well established, model with reality, or the target it is being
used to model.
Another aspect of the nature of science and models is the fact that it is com-
mon for scientist to use multiple models to describe an entity (Flores-Camacho,
Gallegos-Cázares, Garritz, & García-Franco, 2007) or explain phenomena/data
(Barnea, Dori, & Finegold, 1995; Birk & Abbassain, 1996; Lin & Chiu, 2007). The
use of multiple models is particularly prevalent in some sciences such as physics
and chemistry, especially when it comes to developing an understanding of abstract
microscopic concepts like atomic structure and chemical bonding (Brodie et al.,
1994; Chiu, Chou, & Liu, 2002; Comba & Hambley, 1995; Eilam, 2004; Glynn &
Duit, 1995; Lin & Chiu, 2007; Lopes & Costa, 2007). Again, as might be expected,
there are significant differences in how scientists view and use multiple models (see,
e.g., Clement, 1998; Flores-Camacho et al., 2007; Grosslight et al., 1991; Harrison
& De Jong, 2005), with scientists again acting in a highly pragmatic fashion. As
an illustration, there are numerous models for chemical bonding, and scientists
use whichever model seems appropriate and convenient (Coll & Treagust, 2003a,
2003b). Consider reactions of aromatic chemical substances. Molecular orbital the-
ory provides the most comprehensive explanation for the bonding in aromatics (viz,
delocalization of electron density across the molecule), but scientists routinely use
electron dot Lewis structure-type notations and formulae when presenting reaction
schemes (Coll & Treagust, 2002a). Key here, again, is that the scientist retains in his
or her mind an acute appreciation of the limitations that such simple models possess,
and that there are often apparent “contradictions” between models (Flores-Camacho
et al., 2007) because they are used for different purposes.
The final aspect of models related to the nature of science we wish to raise here is
the success or otherwise of models. We have already noted that all models possess