Innateness and Ontology, Part I
122
quotidian concepts, its answers to ‘What is their content?’and to ‘How do
you acquire them?’ are, respectively, ‘It has none’ and ‘You don’t’. It’s
worth bearing in mind that analytic philosophy, from Hume to Carnap
inclusive, was a critical programme. For the Empiricists, the idea was to
constrain the conditions for concept possession a priori, by constraining
the acceptable relations between concepts and percepts. It would then turn
out that you really don’t have many of the concepts that you think you
have; you don’t have GOD, CAUSE, or TRIANGLE at all, and though
perhaps you do have DOG, it’ s not the sort of concept that you had
supposed it to be. “When we run over the libraries, persuaded of these
principles, what havoc must we make?” (Hume 1955: 3.) Post-Positivist
philosophical analysis has wavered between reconstruction and
deconstruction, succeeding in neither. Most practitioners now hold that we
do have DOG, CAUSE, and TRIANGLE after all; maybe even GOD.
But they none the less insist that there are substantive, a priori,
epistemological constraints on concept possession. These, in the fullness
of time, analysis will reveal; to the confusion of Sceptics, Metaphysical
Realists, Mentalists, Cartesians, and the like. Probably of Cognitive
Scientists too.
But, between friends: nothing of the sort is going to happen. In which
case, what’s left to a notion of conceptual analysis that’s detached from its
traditional polemical context? And what on earth are conceptual analyses
for?
Second objection: The informational part of IA says that content is
constituted by nomic symbol-world connections. If that is true, then there
must be laws about everything that we have concepts of. Now, it may be
there are laws about some of the things that we have concepts of (fish,
stars, grandmothers(?!)). But how could there be laws about, as it might be,
doorknobs?
2
Notice that it’s only in conjunction with conceptual atomism
that informational semantics incurs this objection. Suppose the concept
DOORKNOB is definitionally equivalent to the complex concept . . .
ABC . . . Then we can think the former concept if there are laws about
each of the constituents of the latter. In effect, all informational semantics
per se requires for its account of conceptual content is that there be laws
about the properties expressed by our primitive concepts. However, IA says
that practically every (lexical) concept is primitive. So, presumably, it says
that DOORKNOB is primitive.
3
So there must be laws about doorknobs
2
For discussions that turn on this issue, see Fodor 1986; Antony and Levine 1991;
Fodor 1991.
3
Actually, of course, DOORKNOB isn’t a very good example, since it’s plausibly a
compound composed of the constituent concepts DOOR and KNOB. But let’s ignore that
for the sake of the discussion.
Chaps. 5 & 6 11/3/97 1:10 PM Page 122