Restoration: constitutional theory 99
the Dialogue between a philosopher and a student of the common laws of
England, he applied this simple principle to English constitutional ideas.
He decided not to print it (he regarded the end as 'imperfect'), but we know
that he composed it after 1664, and that Hale studied it, in manuscript, at
some time before February of
1673.
1
Our evidence, from a letter of John
Aubrey's, is the tantalising assertion that 'Judge Hales, who is no great
courtier, has read it and much dislikes it, and is his enemy. Judge Vaughan
has read it and much commends it'.
2
Hobbes' principal grievance against the common lawyers, as represented
by Sir Edward Coke, was that they had usurped the sovereign's power. He
gladly agreed, to begin with, that 'nihil quod est rationi contrarium est
licitum; that is to say, nothing is law that is against reason: and that reason
is the life of the law, nay the common law itself is nothing but reason',
3
but he objected to the claim that lawyers possessed the authority by which
this reason was identified:
that the reason which is the life of the law should not be natural but artificial I
cannot conceive. ... I grant you that the knowledge of law is an art, but not that
any art of one man or of many how wise soever they be, or the work of one and
more artificers, how perfect soever it
be,
is law. It
is
not wisdom but authority that
makes a law ... That the law hath been
fined
by grave and learned men, meaning
the professors of
the
law
is
manifestly untrue, for all the laws of England have been
made by the kings of England, consulting with the nobility and commons in
parliament, of which not one in twenty was a learned lawyer.
4
If reason was correctly glossed, however, he was happy with the essence
of Coke's theory: 'he makes the common law and the law of reason to be
all one, as indeed they are, when by it is meant the king's reason'.
5
In
practice, Hobbes seems to have thought, the judges did make laws by
precedent, which was 'tacitly confirmed (because not disapproved) by the
sovereign legislator'.
6
But at all events, there was no call for any skill
unique to professional lawyers. To know the common law, in the world
that Hobbes imagined, was not to have mastered the lawyer's mode of
thought, but to have access to the king's instructions. There was no need
for 'artificial' reason, or any of the rituals of the Inns:
if
I
pretend within a month or two to make myself able to perform the office of a
judge, you are not to think it arrogance; for you are to allow to me, as well as to
other men, my pretence to reason, which is the common law (remember this that I
may need not again to put you in mind, that reason is the common law) and for
1
Its modern editor suggests that it may in fact be finished as it stands (Thomas Hobbes,
A dialogue between a philosopher and a student of the common laws of England, ed.
Joseph Cropsey, Chicago 1971, pp. 2-8).
2
Aubrey's Brief lives, I, 394.
3
Hobbes, Dialogue, 54.
4
Ibid.,
55.
5
Ibid.,
143.
6
Ibid.,
142.